John Levi Martin argues in The Explanation of Social Action, among other things, that we need to understand the social world through the ways it is experienced by participants. "Sociology and its near kin have adopted an understanding of theoretical explanation that privileges 'third-person' explanations and, in particular, have decided that the best explanation is a 'causal' third-person explanation, in which we attribute causal power to something other than flesh-and-blood individuals" (kl 75). He thus criticizes sociological theorizing because it is third-person and aims to explain social arrangements in terms foreign to the participants.
But this is really what the act of "theorizing" always involves, and why it is important. The social world always exceeds the vision of the participants, and though Levi Martin cringes at the thought, there are in fact distant, unseen structures and systems that constrain local experience. The role of theory -- one role, anyway -- is to discover in thought what some of those systemic processes and forces are. "Capitalism," "trading system," "sugar-cotton-slave nexus," "finance capital," and "bourgeois ideology" are all theoretical formulations designed to connect the dots -- to draw attention to the systems within which everyday experience takes place. And those systems exist and have consequences for individuals at all levels of agency -- beliefs, assumptions, purposes, incentives, and constraints.
It is of course true that social entities at every level require microfoundations. So it isn't quite right to say that social entities convey effects through something other than flesh-and-blood individuals. But this does not mean that they do not convey effects onto individuals and local arrangements that are beyond the ken of the local actors.
Take the complex of ideas associated with Marx's conception of materialism as an example, and put yourself in a particular historical setting--say British factory expansion in the 1830s and 1840s. Participants at every location had perceptions and ways of talking about their experiences. The recently "freed" factory worker in Manchester had his perspective; the dockworker in London had his; the "putting-out" spinner had hers; the Caribbean slave had his and hers; and likewise the baker, the tailor, and the candlestick maker. For that matter, Marx, Engels, and Carlyle were participants too, and they made their own efforts to conceptualize and explain their experience. They wanted to say what was going on.
But here is the crucial point; none of them really got it. They got parts of the story -- the harsh conditions in the factory, the swirl of new finance activity, the overseers' whip, the living conditions in slums in Birmingham, Manchester, and London, the stench of the River Irk, and much else. But none was in a position to perceive the relationships among these social locations.
These are all fragments of the picture, and as Marx insisted in Capital when he discussed commodity fetishism -- some of these perspectives conceal rather than expose the system of social relations that was emerging. It took something else in order to cognize "emerging capitalist urban industrial society". Carlyle did his part (he coined the phrase, the "cash nexus"); so did Engels and Marx; and so have Gramsci and Wallerstein. Theorizing was necessary in order to transform the partial and sometimes mystifying bits of ordinary experience into a more revealing system-level understanding. The worker perceives the temporal coercion of the factory; but he and she do not perceive the larger social structures that explained that system of organization.
Is the participant-level even the right perspective from which to try to identify an explanation? I don't think so. Were conditions in this factory harsh because this owner was hostile or cruel towards these particular workers? No, rather because the competitive environment of profitability and accumulation created an inexorable race to the bottom. So we can't explain this factory's working conditions by referring to specific features of this factory and its owner. This logic is spelled out very clearly in Capital, and it is a system-level characteristic.
Here is what Levi Martin has to say about this line of argument, early in ESA. He paraphrases the argument in these words:
Actors may see the little picture -- particularities that while undeniable are still ignorable -- but they do not produce the sweeping abstractions that have important implications across many domains of social life. It is these general abstracts that, when linked in some system, deserve the credit of behing "theory, and the more surprising the implications -- the less they agree with the particular, everyday knowledge of actors -- the more brilliant the theory is if confirmed. (kl 104).It is plain that L-M does not accept this move from the particular local knowledges to a more abstract "theory" that connects the dots. He favors instead a mode of theorizing that derives from phenomenology:
Phenomenology in this sense is the study of how every-day people orient themselves to the world and how they determine what needs to be done. (kl 152)But it is likely that no one within the emerging factory system in Manchester or Birmingham would have experienced the system-level factors that shaped the emergence of that system. The self-conception of the capitalist factory owner is "modernizer," "bringer of better life prospects to immigrant Irish peasants," or "contributor to a new Britain" -- not "cog in a system of profit-maximizing competition where to lose one's footing in pushing costs down is to drown."
So how do distant, impersonal social forces impinge on local experience? This is the nexus that draws the greatest skepticism from Levi Martin. But it isn't particularly difficult to answer. Take the rapid development of tenements and slums that Engels describes in The Condition of the Working Class in England. The expansion of trade, rapidly rising demand for finished goods, and the workings of financial markets are the distal causes that shaped the choices of capitalists, city fathers, and legislators, and these choices compounded to the misery described by Engels. This is the value of Immanuel Wallerstein's work; he helps demonstrate these distal relations and systemic interrelationships (The Modern World-System I: Capitalist Agriculture and the Origins of the European World-Economy in the Sixteenth Century, With a New Prologue). And I don't think that Wallerstein's work is at all incompatible with an actor-centered, microfoundational view of social causation.
2 comments:
Thank you yet again for another stimulating blog entry.
Here is (as far as I know) Marx's clearest statement about the limits of the point of view of any individual capitalist and the need for theory.
Marx, Capital, vol 3.
The theoretical conception concerning the first transformation of surplus-value into profit, that every partof a capital yields a uniform profit, expresses a practical fact. Whatever the composition of an industrialcapital, whether it sets in motion one quarter of congealed labour and three-quarters of living labour, orthree-quarters of congealed labour and one-quarter of living labour, whether in one case it absorbs threetimes as much surplus-labour, or produces three times as much surplus-value than in another -- in eithercase it yields the same profit, given the same degree of labour exploitation and leaving aside individualdifferences, which, incidentally, disappear because we are dealing in both cases with the averagecomposition of the entire sphere of production. The individual capitalist (or all the capitalists in eachindividual sphere of production), whose outlook is limited, rightly believes that his profit is not derivedsolely from the labour employed by him, or in his line of production. This is quite true, as far as hisaverage profit is concerned. To what extent this profit is due to the aggregate exploitation of labour onthe part of the total social capital, i.e., by all his capitalist colleagues -- this interrelation is a completemystery to the individual capitalist; all the more so, since no bourgeois theorists, the political economists,have so far revealed it. A saving of labour -- not only labour necessary to produce a certain product, butalso the number of employed labourers -- and the employment of more congealed labour (constantcapital), appear to be very sound operations from the economic standpoint and do not seem to exert theleast influence on the general rate of profit and the average profit. How could living labour be the solesource of profit, in view of the fact that a reduction in the quantity of labour required for productionappears not to exert any influence on profit? Moreover, it even seems in certain circumstances to be thenearest source of an increase of profits, at least for the individual capitalist"
Rakesh Bhandari
Another example from Marx would be chapters 23-24 of Capital Vol I.
From the perspective of the individual worker, it may seem that the capitalist exchanges value in the form of a wage for her labor time.
But once we look at this exchange as a collective process over time, it becomes clear that the capitalists are withholding value that workers have themselves already produced and need for subsistence until they pledge to perform the number of labor hours required for the on-going appropriation of surplus value.
In other words, from the perspective of the totality over time, it becomes clear that capitalists are strictly speaking exchanging value for the labor time, but withholding value that workers already produced until they consent to on-going exploitation.
Marx does not think that this point of view is readily available to the workers but only comes into view through structural analysis.
R Bhandari
Post a Comment